Menu Top



Analytical School: John Austin



Definition of Law: Command of the Sovereign

Legal Positivism is a school of jurisprudence that holds that the existence and content of law depend on social facts, not on its merits. It emphasises the separation of law as it is (lex lata) from law as it ought to be (de lege ferenda) and is often contrasted with natural law theory.

The Analytical School, primarily associated with Jeremy Bentham and John Austin, is a prominent stream within legal positivism. It focuses on analysing the fundamental concepts of law and legal systems as they exist.


John Austin (1790-1859): The Province of Jurisprudence Determined (1832)

John Austin is considered the father of English Analytical Jurisprudence. He sought to define law precisely and distinguish it from other rules. His core theory, the Command Theory of Law, is a cornerstone of early legal positivism.

Austin defined law strictly as 'a rule laid down for the guidance of an intelligent being by an intelligent being having power over him'. He then narrowed this down to focus on positive law.

According to Austin, positive law is the command of the sovereign, backed by a sanction. This is the central tenet of his theory.


Law as a product of political authority

Austin viewed positive law as entirely a social fact, created by a political authority (the sovereign) in a particular society. Its validity derives solely from its source (the sovereign's command), not from any inherent moral content or connection to natural law principles. He explicitly separated law from morality; a law could be morally unjust but still be valid law if it was a command from the sovereign.


Sanction as an essential element

Austin argued that a command is effective as law only if it is backed by the threat of a sanction. A sanction is an evil or punishment that is likely to follow from disobedience to the command. This threat of punishment is what creates a duty to obey the law.

Thus, for Austin, law is essentially a system of commands, duties, and threatened punishments originating from a determinate political superior.



Components of Austin's Theory

Austin's command theory can be broken down into its core components: Sovereign, Command, Duty, and Sanction.


Sovereign

According to Austin, the sovereign is a determinate human superior who is habitually obeyed by the bulk of a given society, and who himself habitually obeys no other human superior.


Command

A command is an expression of a wish or desire by a superior, coupled with the power to inflict an evil or suffering in case of disobedience. Not all commands are laws. Laws properly so-called are general commands issued by the sovereign.

Austin distinguished between laws properly so-called (commands of the sovereign) and laws improperly so-called (like laws of fashion, international law as it existed then, which lacked a sovereign enforcer).


Duty

A duty, in Austin's theory, is the obligation to obey the command of the sovereign. It is created by the likelihood of incurring the threatened sanction in case of disobedience. Duty is correlative to command; where there is a command, there is a duty to obey.


Sanction

A sanction is the evil or punishment attached to the command, which is imposed for disobedience. It is the motivational force behind obedience to the law. Without a threatened sanction, according to Austin, a command is not a law properly so-called.

Austin's theory thus presents a simple, stark model of law as hierarchical commands backed by force, issued by an ultimate political superior.



Classification of Law

Austin's definition of law led him to classify various rules and norms, distinguishing what he considered 'positive law' from other forms of rules.


Laws Properly So Called vs. Laws Improperly So Called:

Austin's main classification divides rules into:

Human Law (Positive Law, Positive Morality)

Austin further divided Human Law (commands set by men to men) into:

By this classification, Austin sought to delineate the specific domain of legal science – positive law – from other normative systems like divine law or positive morality.



Criticism of Austin's Theory

Despite its influence, Austin's command theory has faced significant criticism for its oversimplification of the nature of law and legal systems.


Criticism related to laws as commands, duties, and sanctions


Criticism related to Sovereignty


Criticism related to the role of custom and morality

Austin's theory provides a simple starting point for understanding positive law but fails to capture the complexity, diversity, and normative nature of modern legal systems. Subsequent legal positivists, like Hart and Kelsen, developed more sophisticated theories to address these criticisms.



H.L.A. Hart's Pure Theory of Law



Concept of Law as Union of Primary and Secondary Rules

H.L.A. Hart (Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart) is one of the most important legal philosophers of the 20th century. In his seminal work, 'The Concept of Law' (1961), he presented a sophisticated version of legal positivism, building upon and significantly critiquing Austin's command theory.

Hart viewed law as a system of social rules, fundamentally different from Austin's model of commands. His central concept is that a mature legal system is a union of primary and secondary rules.


Primary Rules: Duty-imposing

Primary rules are those that directly impose duties on individuals regarding their actions or forbearances. They tell people what they are obligated to do or not to do (e.g., rules of criminal law prohibiting theft, rules of tort law imposing duties of care).

In a simple society without a developed legal system, there might only be primary rules. However, such a system would suffer from certain defects:


Secondary Rules: Power-conferring

To remedy the defects of a system based solely on primary rules, secondary rules are necessary. Secondary rules are rules about rules. They do not impose duties directly but confer powers, public or private, to create, modify, or extinguish primary rules, or to determine their violation.

Hart identified three types of secondary rules:

  1. Rule of Recognition: This is the most important secondary rule. It specifies the criteria for identifying what counts as valid law within a particular legal system. It provides the ultimate rule for determining the validity of primary rules. In a complex legal system, the rule of recognition might be complex, referring to criteria like legislative enactment, judicial precedent, constitutional provisions, etc. Its existence is a matter of social fact, evidenced by the practice of officials (judges, lawyers, administrators) in identifying and applying valid laws.

  2. Rule of Change: These rules empower individuals or bodies (like legislatures) to introduce new primary rules, repeal old ones, or modify existing ones. They remedy the static character of a system based only on primary rules (e.g., rules governing the legislative process).

  3. Rule of Adjudication: These rules confer power on individuals (like judges) to determine authoritatively whether a primary rule has been violated and to impose sanctions. They remedy the inefficiency of a system lacking formal mechanisms for dispute resolution (e.g., rules of evidence and procedure).

For Hart, a legal system exists when its officials accept and follow the secondary rules (particularly the rule of recognition) from an 'internal point of view' (i.e., seeing them as standards of behaviour and justification) and the bulk of the population obeys the primary rules.

This theory provided a more nuanced and accurate picture of legal systems than Austin's command theory, accounting for different types of laws and the internal aspect of rules.



Minimum Content of Natural Law

While advocating for the conceptual separation of law and morality (legal positivism), Hart acknowledged that any viable legal system must contain a certain minimum moral content. This he referred to as the minimum content of natural law.


The five truths about human nature

Hart argued that this minimum content is necessary because of certain universal truths about human nature and the conditions of life. He listed five such 'truisms' or facts:

  1. Human vulnerability: Humans are vulnerable to physical attack. This necessitates rules restricting the use of violence.

  2. Approximate equality: No single individual is so powerful as to dominate others without cooperation. This makes mutual forbearances necessary.

  3. Limited altruism: Humans are neither angels nor devils. They are capable of both good and bad acts. Rules are needed to restrain harmful behaviour and ensure cooperation.

  4. Limited resources: Resources are scarce, necessitating rules governing property and distribution.

  5. Limited understanding and strength of will: Not all humans are rational or capable of self-control. This makes sanctions necessary as guarantees that those who would voluntarily submit to the rules are not sacrificed to those who would not.

These facts, combined with the human goal of survival, make a minimum set of rules protecting persons, property, and promises universally necessary for any system of social order to endure. Hart argued that these are not absolute moral dictates in a metaphysical sense, but necessary conditions for survival, making a minimum overlap between law and morality a reality, not a conceptual necessity for legal validity.

This concept showed that Hart's positivism was more open to considering the relationship between law and human nature than earlier positivist theories.



Distinction between Law and Morals

A core tenet of legal positivism, and specifically Hart's theory, is the distinction between law and morals. This is known as the separation thesis.


Separation Thesis

The separation thesis asserts that there is no necessary connection between law and morality. This means:

Hart argued for the conceptual separation of law and morality. He believed that understanding law requires analysing its structure as a system of rules and its basis in social practice (especially the acceptance of the rule of recognition by officials), independent of moral evaluation.

However, Hart acknowledged the many ways in which law and morality do interact in practice:

Despite these interactions, Hart maintained that the definition and identification of law are distinct from its moral evaluation. This separation allows for clarity in understanding what the law is, even if one believes it is morally wrong. It also encourages a critical moral attitude towards law, as judging law requires a standard external to law itself.



Criticism of Hart's Theory

Despite its sophistication, Hart's theory has also faced criticism, notably from legal philosopher Ronald Dworkin.


Dworkin's Critique (Principles vs. Rules)

Ronald Dworkin (1931-2013) presented a major challenge to Hart's positivism in his work 'Taking Rights Seriously' (1977).

Dworkin used famous cases like Riggs v. Palmer (where a murderer was denied inheritance despite a valid will, based on the principle that no one should profit from their own wrong) to argue that principles, which have a moral character, are integral to the legal system and constrain judicial decisions even when rules might suggest a different outcome.

Dworkin's critique led to extensive debates within legal philosophy about the nature of law, the role of judges, and the relationship between law and morality, prompting responses and refinements from positivists like Joseph Raz.



Hans Kelsen: Pure Theory of Law



Concept of Law as a Normative Science

Hans Kelsen (1881-1973), an Austrian jurist and philosopher, is another highly influential figure in legal positivism. His 'Pure Theory of Law' (Reine Rechtslehre) aims to provide a rigorous and 'pure' description of law, free from any foreign elements like morality, sociology, or history.


Pure Theory:

Kelsen sought to identify the essential nature of law as a system of coercive norms. His theory is 'pure' because it seeks to isolate law from all non-legal disciplines and focus solely on the nature of legal norms and their structure within a legal system.

Law as a System of Norms:

For Kelsen, law is a system of norms. A norm is a rule that prescribes a certain behaviour and attaches a consequence (usually a sanction) to non-compliance. Legal norms are distinguished from other norms (e.g., moral norms) by their coercive character; they are backed by the threat of state-imposed sanctions.

Kelsen focused on the validity of norms. A norm is valid if it is authorised by a higher norm within the legal system. This leads to a hierarchical structure of legal norms.


Grounded Norm (Grundnorm)

The hierarchical structure of legal norms must ultimately rest on a basic, foundational norm that provides the basis for the validity of the entire legal system. Kelsen called this the 'Grundnorm' or Basic Norm.


Hierarchy of Norms

According to Kelsen, a legal system is a dynamic system of norms structured in a hierarchy, like a pyramid.

Each norm in the hierarchy is valid because it is authorised by a higher norm. The entire system is unified by the Grundnorm.

Kelsen's theory is sometimes called the 'normative theory' because it views law as a system of 'oughts' or norms, in contrast to descriptive theories like Austin's command theory.



Separation of Law and Morals

A central feature of Kelsen's Pure Theory is the strict separation of law and morals. Like other positivists, Kelsen argued that the validity of a legal norm does not depend on its moral content.


Strict Separation:

Kelsen believed that separating law from morality was essential for a pure and objective science of law, free from subjective moral evaluations.



Criticism of Kelsen's Theory

Kelsen's Pure Theory, while intellectually rigorous, has also faced criticisms:


Criticism related to the Grundnorm:

Criticism related to the pureness of the theory:

Despite these criticisms, Kelsen's theory remains a significant contribution to legal positivism for its systematic and hierarchical view of legal norms and its rigorous attempt to define law based on its own internal structure.



Legal Positivism: Key Thinkers and Concepts



HLA Hart's Concept of Law

H.L.A. Hart is a central figure in modern legal positivism, whose work provided a powerful alternative to earlier command theories and significantly shaped contemporary legal philosophy.


Key Contributions:

Hart's theory is influential for its sociological grounding (rule of recognition as a social practice), its nuanced understanding of different types of laws, and its clear distinction between the existence of law and its moral merit. His work is a cornerstone for understanding contemporary legal positivism.



Hans Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law

Hans Kelsen represents a different, more abstract and normative approach within legal positivism, aiming for a scientifically 'pure' understanding of law.


Key Contributions:

Kelsen's theory is significant for its logical consistency and its focus on the formal structure of legal systems. It provides a distinct analytical framework for understanding law as a self-contained normative system.



Joseph Raz: Authority and Legal Positivism

Joseph Raz (1939-2022) is another leading figure in contemporary legal positivism, who developed a sophisticated theory based on the concept of authority.


Key Contributions:

Raz's work built upon Hart's foundation, offering a powerful defence of legal positivism rooted in the concept of authority and its practical implications for identifying and obeying law. His emphasis on the authoritative nature of law reinforced the idea that law's validity is a matter of social fact, identifiable by its sources.

Together, the theories of Austin, Hart, Kelsen, and Raz represent the diverse landscape of legal positivism, each offering distinct insights into the nature and identification of law while sharing the core commitment to separating law from morality.